I had the great pleasure of taking part in CogSci 2012. Below you will find impressions from the conference, and links for further reading. Wonderful stuff! Certainly, I'm already looking forward to CogSci 2013 in Berlin! The conference was held in Sapporo, Japan. Sapporo is the fourth-largest city in Japan by population, and the largest city on the island of Hokkaido. |
The Main Hall can easily accommodate large conferences and is innovatively styled as a multi-purposes venue.
The Conference Hall creates an impressive atmosphere. It is equipped with simultaneous interpretation system for six languages. It has a capacity of 700, and can be used for international conferences, as well as other meetings and congresses.
What is thought? How can we describe the intelligent inferences made in everyday human reasoning and learning? How can we engineer intelligent machines? The computational theory of mind aims to answer these questions starting from the hypothesis that the mind is a computer, mental representations are computer programs, and thinking is a computational process running a computer program.It will here be assumed that mental representations are like theories:
There are facts and rules.And we can take random walks through program executions, and see where we might end up.
Then we can ask - if this is the end-state, what was the start-state or
if this is the start-state, what is the end-state.
In 1943 he wrote The Nature of Explanation. In this book he laid the foundation for the concept of mental models, that the mind forms models of reality and uses them to predict similar future events. He was one of the earliest practitioners of cognitive science.About 1980, Johnson Laird and Gentner and Stevens puiblished books about mental models. Viewing cognition as simulation //but they didn't have all the computational tools to formalize this grand theory the way we have now //.
According to a standard humor appreciation model (Suls, 1972; Wyer & Collins, 1992; Yus, 2003; Martin, 2006), incongruities in the content of the utterance must be identified and resolved for it to be humorous. The incongruities are typically caused by violation of a set of expectations stored in ''mental schemas'' which are ''formed on the basis of past experience with objects, scenes, or events and consists of a set of (usually unconscious) expectations about what things look like and/or the order in which they occur''.See paper.
We propose that activation of amygdala in humor appreciation can be interpreted as the result of detecting the optimal relevance in humorous utterances - the ''aha'' reaction.Where,
Lesion and neuroimaging studies have shown that the amygdala is involved in an evaluation of motivationally relevant events... We argue that the amygdala is a candidate for relevance-based processing.The authors found that when a participant judged something humorous, the bilateral amygdala had been significantly activated (at the 4th phase of its processing). But banal (non-humorous) events are also detected by the amygdala, somewhat earlier though.
The nature of human conceptual processing and its roles in perception, memory, language, and thought. The current theme of his research is that the conceptual system is grounded in the brain's modal systems for perception, action, and internal states.And what a super interesting talk (about situated conceptualization) it turned out to be!
Specific topics of current interest include the roles of conceptual processing in emotion, self, stress, abstract thought, and contemplative practices.
His research also addresses the role of mental simulation in conceptual processing, the situated and embodied nature of knowledge, the dynamic online construction of conceptual representations, the development of conceptual systems to support goal achievement, and the structure of knowledge.
Concepts are not typically processed in isolation but are typically situated in background settings.Whenever you think of a concept ''dog'' you also think about the situation that you might find this dog in. We represent a lot of background information. I.e. the brain is a situated processing unit.
When representing a bicycle, for example, people do not represent a bicycle in isolation but represent it in relevant situations.
Even when people focus attention on a particular entity or event in perception, they continue to perceive the background situation, the situation does not disappear.
The cognitive system produces many different situated conceptualizations of bicycle, each tailored to help an agent interact with bicycles in different situations. For example, one situated conceptualization for bicycle might support riding a bicycle, whereas others might support locking a bicycle, repairing a bicycle and so forth. On this view, the concept for bicycle is not a single generic representation of the category. Instead, the concept is the skill or ability to produce a wide variety of situated conceptualizations that support goal achievement in specific contexts.Concepts might not just reside in episodic or semantic centers. Instead e.g. the concept for tool might be emergent as interplay between a lot of centers processing different properties of tools.
By re-enacting actions and introspections from a particular perspective, a situated conceptualization creates the experience of the conceptualizer being in the situation. The situation is not represented as detached and separate from the conceptualizer [1].
Theories of emotion propose that an agent continually evaluates a situation and that the result of the evaluation leads to emotion. The evaluation is hypothesized to take place along multiple dimensions, such as goal relevance (is this situation important to my goals?), goal conductiveness (is this situation good or bad for my goals?), causality (who caused the situation?), control (can I change the situation?), and so on. These dimensions are exactly what an intelligent agent needs to compute as it pursues its goals while interacting with an environment.
Perhaps the most pressing issue surrounding this area of work is the lack of well specified computational accounts. Our understanding of simulators, simulations, situated conceptualizations and pattern completion inference would be much deeper if computational accounts specified the underlying mechanisms. Increasingly, grounding such accounts in neural mechanisms is obviously important as well, as is designing increasingly sophisticated experiments to assess and develop these accounts [2].Could anything be more exciting?
These results indicate that participants do not in fact terminate search over-quickly in open - relative to closed - interval designs. Furthermore, as participants were able to retrieve the same amount of items in less time, the results suggest that the open-interval design might provide a method to measure not only how memory is searched, but also how efficiently memory can be searched.
Heuristics are necessary for good decisions. Complex problems do not require complex solutions. Less is more.Mervyn King (Bank of England) has suggested that a simple rule like:
Don't use leverage above 10:1.(Wiki: Leverage, sometimes referred to as gearing in the United Kingdom, or solvency in Australia)
Don't buy financial products you don't understand.Nick Chater continued with a talk about ''Why didn't the markets self-correct?''. Seeing the Economic Crisis as an information failure.
-Simon
Simon Laub
www.simonlaub.net